So far as the institution for which he labored is concernednamely,
a public school system supported by public taxation and open to all children,
training schools for teachers, and so onthe dream of Horace Mann
... has in the passage of a hundred years been realized to a surprising
degree. But the problem ... is still with us. We have now the institutions
which he strove to bring into being. But we still have with us, and perhaps
in an even more urgent and difficult way, the problem of how this institution
is to be made to serve the needs of democratic society. (Dewey [1937]
1958: 46)
In the first lecture, I presented a view of culture as a dialogical
process producing concrete objects. I used the metaphor of the house built
on a landscape for human beings to inhabit. In the second lecture, I extended
the metaphor to emphasize the complex activities around the building,
repairing and rebuilding of this house. Over the centuries, this process
produced a particularity in human history: "American" education.
It would of course be more evocative to think of this object as a city
with its many buildings and institutions, and particularly its schools.
This city embodies in its very organization a set of properties that,
in the long run, constrain action in the United States, particularly on
the most public stages. Furthermore, collective action acknowledging these
constraints end up reconstituting them for future generations.
Those who know the history of the United States will recognize
that my talk of America as city is a deliberate echo of the use the classical
Biblical image of the "city upon a hill" that was appropriated
by American Protestant utopians to give a messianic tone to their visions.
In my own appropriation of the image, China, India, the Muslim world,
all also stand as "cities upon hills," unavoidable to all who
approach them. This is not a return to the 19th century "orientalism"
Said criticized. Rather it is an acknowledgement of the ideological, as
well as commercial and military, power of America (and of course China,
India, etc.) outside its boundaries as well as inside.
I also made the point that these properties are best revealed at moments
of controversies when boundaries are tested and institutions are reconstructed
because they can no longer quite stand exactly as they were before. And
I made the point that when talking about America and American education
I am not referring mostly to psychological processes involving knowledge
or values. Rather I am referring to institutions with long histories that
have radically transformed what human beings in the United States, and
now around the world, have to deal with. In this last lecture I continue
to focus on controversies to discern more clearly the sometimes fateful
consequences of these properties as they both enable and disable possibilities
for human beings.
To summarize briefly, the strongest properties of America involve matters
such as:
the primacy of the individualinstitutionalized in such things
as tests to determine the exact qualities of the person, intellectually
or emotionally;
the view of society as community of like-minded individualsinstitutionalized
in all sorts of programs to build particular kinds of persons;
the understanding that this requires specific activitiesinstitutionalized
in complex schools organized around intellectual and emotional curricula.
Depending on how I present this argument, I will be accused, in an American
context, particularly within the discipline of anthropology, of "substantializing"
America. For the critics, to do so would make us lose sight both of the
made-up character of America and of the multiplicity of Americas co-existing
within the boundaries of the United States. To these criticisms, I answer
that I take more seriously than most the principle that human beings are
indeed at work constructing their world in uncertainty and controversy.
I also take most seriously the fact that, if this is the case, then there
must be some remnants of this work that new comers cannot ignore. To emphasize
as I do the concreteness of this historical work is not to de-emphasize
multiplicity. On the contrary it allows for a more complex understanding
of multiplicity and unity. An emphasis on America as institution allows
one to point at all the open spaces for special constructions. It also
allows to insist that persons are not determined by their encounters with
the more massive cultural objects they find on their way.
Most of my work has been a reaction against a particular way of talking
about culture that even the most vocal critics of cultural analyses continue
using matter-of-factly. Note that I never talked about "Americans"
because I fear that, to do so is to postulate more or less explicitly
a uniformity of mind among the population of the United States that is
unwarranted methodologically as well as theoretically: After all I do
not know most Americans and do not trust any of the methodologieseven
the statistical ones that might produce statements like "90% of Americans
believe in God." Thus, I fight any view of culture that collapse
the products of history into personal agents with specifiable attitudes
or beliefs learned early in life or developed at a later stage. I do so
to emphasize the distinctiveness of what local populations can build over
centuries as it gets to stand against what other populations build. I
do so to emphasize the productivity of people with their cultural environment,
their resistance to it, their appropriation of some of it, their successes
in carving spaces when some constraints fail to apply, and so on an so
forth. America is powerful but it is not overwhelming internally.
Let us go back briefly to my metaphor of America as a city built up in
controversy over many centuries. Once, the French anthropologist Claude
Lévi-Strauss wrote about culture as a "palace carried by a
flood with its parts reorganized by new stresses no architect could have
anticipated" (paraphrase [1962] 1966: ). I also like a poem
by the American poet Robert Frost puzzling about the need to reconstruct
arbitrary walls. As Frost puts it "Something there is that doesn't
love a wall." All cultural constructions, from walls between neighboring
properties to schools, are shaky. They are in need of continual reconstruction.
In this lecture I focus on "what there is that does not love a culture,"
that is on the stresses that continue to threaten what has been constructed
so far and might eventually lead to its collapse. I will do this from
two points of view. First, I will start with difficulties that are specifically
identified by dominant or emergent political voices. Second, I will move
on to point at stresses that are the direct product of the very shape
of the overall building. These are stresses that could not be relieved
without pulling the whole down and, in the process, tearing apart much
that is indeed very good. These structural stresses are particularly visible
in institutionalized education and they cannot be ignored. But we cannot
ignore either the beauty or wisdom of what these stresses allow. Culture
does disable in particular ways. But it also enables in the very same
ways. There lies a potential for drama if not tragedy of which we have
many examples in the actual history of the United States. For all who
deal with America, there is no escaping what might be approached as an
internal contradiction that is also a creative tension keeping the civilization
alive.
Self-critiques
America has produced strong critiques of itself based on self-interpretations
that, over the course of its history have had strong institutional impact.
These continue to be debated, often passionately, among those with the
most authority to rebuild its institutions whether directly through political
action, or indirectly through ideological action. I will only mention
a few that have had distinct impacts on American education.
local self-determination by communities and parents: its value and necessary
limits;
the apparent failures of schools to teach what is needed to compete
internationally;
the integration of new immigrants;
the continued segmentation of all aspects of human society along racial
or quasi-racial lines;
Let us start with one of the more classical self-interpreted worries.
When America was still in the early stages of its building, Jefferson
wondered whether large, industrial, cities were compatible with the realization
of democracy as local self-determination. In many ways the problem is
now moot. Most of the population of the United States lives in such urban
centers and find themselves very far removed from the day to day government
of their towns, cities or states. Above all, through a particularly bloody
civil war and its aftermaths, it became established that there are significant
boundaries limiting local self-determination: no American state can allow
slavery or segregation within its boundaries. Neither can it allow a host
of other matters. America, as sovereign within the territories of the
United States, continues to affirm itself against personal beliefs if
those seek to transform themselves from speech (which is protected) into
action (which it subject to review). Jefferson himself worked to establish
this understanding of American democracy. And yet, to this day, there
are renewed calls to allow for local self-determination, whether at the
"State" level (this is generally considered a "conservative"
position) or at the sub-group level (this is generally considered a "liberal"
position if the group is presented as an ethnic or minority one). It is
not quite a matter of chance that so many large governmental agencies
should be referred to as "community" mattersfor example
"community school boards" in New York City that were the product
of what was known in the 1960s as "decentralization." The power
of such words suggests a nostalgia for a society of small self-determining
groups. The theme of self-determination may be most useful at this point
in discussions of school "vouchers" as a means a letting parents
decide what schools their children should attend. This has put new fire
in the alternative theme that all Americans must operate by the same rules
determined by the political centers.
I will only mention in passing the perennial worries in America about
whether its internal processes produce an adequate level of skill in its
children. For many generations, the American media, political and intellectual
elite, and those who take them on, have worried that in one way or another,
America did not measure up to any number of others (Russia, Japan, China,
India, etc.). These debates, in many ways, echo those about the implication
of the continual reconstruction of America as a land where new people
keep on arriving and settling in. For the sake of brevity, I will spend
more time on these matters, focusing again on continuing controversies
over what policies to adopt to deal with those who have not been acknowledged
as part of the development of America and appear to the dominant elites
as "problems." I have talked at some length in the second lecture
about immigrants to the United States at the end of the 19th century triggering
a reconstitution of the democratic public school along "progressive"
lines. By the late 20th century immigrants from new parts of the world
reopened the debate about the exact shape of the schools, and this new
movement of population would have been enough to trigger a new reconstitution
of the school. But the main issues of the past 50 years have centered
on the political reinterpretation of the place of marginalized populations
in the schools, particularly Blacks, Mexicans in the South West, or American
Indians. Starting with the Supreme Court declaring school segregation
unconstitutional in Brown vs. Board of Education, all aspects of American
schooling had to reconstitute itself in a different political climate.
For any number of reasons, by the 70s and 80s it was agreed by most (but
certainly not all) in the elites, that this reconstruction should proceed
through a reconstitution of "difference" not as something to
be erased in the building of American selves, but rather as something
to be celebrated, and then subsumed in a general agreement to live in
mutual respect of these differences (Banks 1996). In this model, America
is to be "multicultural" in the same way perhaps as Jefferson
insisted that it be multi-denominational: no national religion, no national
language, no national "culture."
The issue of language is particularly contentious. Thus, we have people
arguing, on the language side, that it is best for immigrants to learn
English as soon as possible so that they can fully enter the labor force.
This is often the position of the migrants themselves except perhaps when
they are very numerous from any one country and congregated in one place
where they can eke a living even by continuing to use their old language.
The Chinese were notorious for maintaining their language as they formed
into "Chinatowns." Spanish speakers have been the flashpoint
since the 1960s when some of their leaders were successful in getting
laws passed requiring, on technical pedagogical grounds, that their children
should be educated in Spanish. In the past five years the other argument
has been powerfully reintroduced. On various other technical grounds it
can be said that bilingual education, as it was implemented in most large
school systems, do not easily produce good English speakers. Some argue
about the validity of these studies, but all know, eventually, that the
issue is an ideological one: is America a neutral ground within which
small groups can self-constitute in the privacy of their own covenants?
Or, is America a particular ground requiring particular kinds of people
educated in particular ways?
In the long run however, the more significant self-critique centers on
the propriety of the distinctions among human beings that were inherited
by early America from Europe. Many of the other matters I have mentioned
appear to yield to reformist moves. Not so the matters where the identification
of individuals as somehow "different" interact with the social
rewards to give them, a process in which the schools are thoroughly implicated.
In the early years, matters of class and race were plausibly most salient.
These have remained, along with matters of gender, disability status,
etc, that raise the same fundamental questions about the legitimacy of
difference in initial identification and social recognition through schooling
and employment.
Structural contradictions
It is with some trepidation that I move on to this discussion of what
I consider to be the structural contradictions that the self-critiques
I just summarized in fact reconstitute. To try to capture America in an
epigram, I would say that America is where the individual is text and
the community context. If so, then everything that is social must be mediated
through psychological processes. To this day it makes sense in America
to say that, given any conflict, the solution must proceed through a change
in "the mind and hearts" of the people involved. This formulation
was at the core of American propaganda during the Vietnam war and it was
intended to represent the ideological goal for the war. There is every
evidence that those who supported the war, and those who opposed it, accepted
this formula as uniquely meaningful. And it remains a powerful guide for
policy, particularly in the context of the more divisive troublesperhaps
more notably on issues of race: To achieve the American utopia, one must
first change the minds and hearts of people and this must be the first
principle of all enlightened policy. Race, in this perspective, has to
do with racism and the best ways to deal with racism involve a personal
change, best achieved through education and, most fatefully, the schools.
Indeed we could see the whole development of the School as the dominant
institution that it has become as the secondary institutional effect of
this idea: Citizens (individuals in a democracy) must be personally developed
for the political system to work as designed. In this manner the physical
dominance of the community school that I mentioned in my first lecture
is indeed indicative of its structural place: No Democracy without a School,
and, more specifically, no Democracy without schools dedicated to shaping
minds and hearts.
This statement, and its embodiment in massive institutions, is one of
the glories of America in that it has enabled millions of people over
the generations to achieve personal lives that they would never have been
able to achieve otherwise. It has also enabled the development of new
knowledge and technologies that might not have been developed otherwise.
It is also profoundly disabling in particular ways that represent the
fundamental dilemma inscribed at the roots of America. The starkest version
of this argument was made by a French anthropologist, Louis Dumont, as
he tried to explain the Indian caste system to a Euro-American audience
(1970 [1966]). On the American side he tried to understand why, until
the Civil War at least, America continually produced theories that branded
slaves as less than human. There have been slaves throughout world history,
and only the most determined efforts by international agencies prevent
the practice from coming back. But America is distinctive in its concern
with trying to justify the status of slave as having something to do with
the inner constitution of the slave as person. This was most infamously
written into the original American constitution as the 3/5 theory of slavery:
slaves in the Southern States would be counted as 3/5 of human beings
for census purposes. Throughout the 19th century, and in fact to this
day, the social placement of Africans at the bottom of the social hierarchy
in the United States was justified on the grounds that Africans were not,
in a fundamental way, the human equal of other humans. Most starkly, if
all human beings were created equal, but some appear so obviously unequal,
then it must be because they are not quite as human as they appear.
Very few people in the United States at this point dare write about human
inequality in this manner--though it continues to happen and to be well-received
in some circles (The Bell Curve Herrnstein & Murray, New York: The
Free Press, 1994). However, in the 150 years since slavery was abolished
and the formal humanity of the slaves was recognized, there has been an
ever renewed effort to explain away social inequalities as somehow produced,
or least mediated, by matters of personal constitution. In several of
our papers, Ray McDermott and I have argued that there is something radically
misleading in all explanations of school failure because they proceed
as if what is an institutionally sanctioned event were a purely psychological
event at the moment when the failure is noticed and acted upon. In the
perspective we criticize, if someone fails a test, it has to do with some
flaw in the person taking the testand not with the criteria used
by the person grading the test and not with the institutions requiring
the test. If someone spends his life in a working class occupation, it
must have to do with the fact that he failed, or dropped out of schooland
not with the fact that his practical conditions made it necessary for
him to start working early. There are profound disagreements about the
exact mechanism of the psychological mediation. With recent advances in
genetics there is a return to biology even though it is most closely related
to classical racism. Most common at this point is the emphasis on social
environmental determination through the transformation of the self (malnutrition,
lack of an intellectual atmosphere in early childhood, etc.). Quite popular
over the past 30 years has been emphases on the "cultural" environment
(through the "learning" of different interactional patterns
that cannot be easily unlearned). Curing these problems may involve all
sorts of reformist solutions (genetic manipulation, food distribution,
improvement in access to medical resources, earlier schooling, programs
to reeducate teachers, etc.) but looking at these solutions reveal again
the movement back to individuals reconstituted as the carrier to their
social difficulties. Noone in America wants to be accused of "blaming
the victim" of social difficulties, but the easier explanations to
convey, and the easier ones to transform into policy always refocus attention
on the victim.
This must be mentioned here since, as the 20th century has progressed
the School has become more and more directly implicated in identifying
and justifying distinctions and identifications with major impacts on
the lives of all in the United States. To use a stark example, IQ measurements
started as a research tool. Soon after, most researchers lost interest
as cognitive psychology, whether in the traditions of Piaget or Vigotsky
moved on to other more complex approaches. But IQ testing perdured in
schools as it, in barely altered forms, continue to provide the legitimizing
basis of the segregation that proceeds through the school. There is good
reasons for this: All histories of IQ tests, and myriad others, point
to their initial identification as a tool of democracy that would finally
allow true, basic and authentic merit to shine through the privileges
of birth. Aptitude testing was a tool that could be held independent from
the prejudices of teachers and administrators. This testing would settle
who is more meritorious and the social problem of unjust segregation would
be resolved. It took a very long time for people to recognize that IQ
tests (and endless variations on the original tests) were not quite blind
to the categorical properties of individuals: whites often did better
than blacks, but the differences disappeared if social conditions were
taken into account. By the 1970s at least a strong critique of all forms
of testing as necessarily insidious was developed but it mostly produced
a continuing recasting of the testsnot a recasting of the cultural
structures that make tests commonsensical. It is has if, to this day,
the American dilemma would be resolved if it could be shown that members
of all groups, however they were defined, failed (and succeeded) equally.
Perhaps most invidious was the development of alternative explanations
for individual difference in performance that did focus on social and
cultural contexts but only as determining context. I have been most interested
in theories of difference that refer one back to "culture" or
"habitus" since they are closest to my disciplinary background
and I see it as my personal responsibility to attack them directly. In
their simplest forms, this theory proposes that much identified failure
in schools was the product of personal mistmatches between the interactional
styles of teachers and students, styles that they would have learned in
"their" culture (Heath 1983). In their most complex forms, this
theory proposes that social differentiation can only be successful if
the people at the bottom get specifically convinced, in institutions that
they cannot challengeparticularly the School--, that their position
is legitimate and thus that they have no grounds for complaint (Bourdieu
and Passeron [1970] 1977). In both cases social differentiation is mediated
by a psychological process or learning or internalization that is both
cause and effect. One American cliche is particularly insidious. It states
that "all societies are made of individuals." If this were true,
it would follow that all social differentiations must have roots in the
individuals of the society, whether as perpetrator or victim. But this
does not follow: social differentiations are the production of particular
collective histories.
Cultural psychological theories have become so successful in educational
circles that they all but displaced purely psychological theories, particularly
the cognitive ones that have been building on Thorndike's work. And yet
they continue to push to the side any analysis, and then any policy development,
that would recognize that the social differentiation characteristic of
large (post-)industrial societies have little to do with personal qualities.
Slavery, most now agree, was not the product of the inferiority of Africans.
Rather it was the product of the organization of the agricultural system
developed in the South of the United States, and its end coincided with
the shift from a rural to an industrial infrastructure. This is the very
industrial, or post-industrial, system that continues to produce different
positions for human beings to inhabit (from the position of janitor to
the position of president). What America adds to this is particular system
for recruiting people into the various positions. This is a system that
places a particular kind of school as the preeminent credentialing institution.
In America, the "people" gives the School the right to grant
degrees to which "privileges" are attachedas an inscription
at the very top of Columbia University's central building remind all who
work there. And at the core of the School stands the Test that identifies
and discriminates. All these matters are institutional matters. They are
cultural matters in my sense.
The Reconstitution of American Democracy
I do not want to end these lectures on a pessimistic note, nor even a
realist note. The concern of America with the individual as constituted
in the School can be shown as specifically disabling human beings in all
sorts of insidious way. And yet institutionalized concern with the individual,
particularly as constituted through the School, also enables human beings
in particularly powerful ways. From Horace Mann to John Dewey, to even
the most ascerbic critics of the implementation of progressive education,
there is a unanimity that I refuse to represent as misunderstanding or
worse. Mann, Dewey and all the others are not the more or less unwitting
tools of the ruling classes. If we, like them, are to take the position
of the constructing critics, then we must recognize the legitimacy of
their own efforts to build particular institutions. Even if there is evidence
that old elites somehow coopted their efforts, it would be more coherent
to see this cooptation as specific work by these elites made necessary
by the work of the critics in a dialogical process that noone can directly
control.
Anthropologists from America looking at the rest of the world have kept
making the point that there is beauty and wisdom everywhere and all can
learn from all even when, often, there is no way that a local collectivity
could try adopt what it is that some other collectivity, "over there"
in some geographical or historical distance, are doingif only because
it can offend justifiably held values or radically disrupt fundamental
institutions. As a native of France who first discovered America from
afar, I remember the time when I saw it, not so naively, as beautiful.
At this point in my life, I would say that it continues to inspire awea
word that, in English, indexes both amazement and danger: what inspires
awe can be also be "awful." There is something awe-inspiring
at the idea of placing at the core of one's political institutions the
School, as a place, run authoritatively by intellectual (rather than commercial,
bureaucratic, or religious) forces, that all children must inhabit for
many years of their lives. This experiment in human possibilities continues
to be overwhelmingly appealing, and not only within the boundaries of
the United States.
And yet, of course the paradox remains. The democratic ideology that
has been so successful in so many ways is exactly the same ideology that
constitutes what remains its core failure. In the context of schooling,
as it is experienced in and out of schools, in the details of everybody's
everyday life in the United States, my colleague Ray McDermott and I proposed
that, in order to help individuals one should not look at them but rather
at the mechanisms that makes them stand out as specialwhether positively
or not (Varenne and McDermott 1998). This is a hard thing to say in Americaanalytically
as well as personally. To turn away from the individual, even if only
for research purposes, will appear, within America, as a scandal. And
yet, every time I reread John Dewey's "Pedagogical Creed," I
flinch when I come to the sentence "I believe that the only true
education comes through the stimulation of the child's powers by the demands
of the social situations in which he finds himself" because it draws
my attention to the "child's powers" to be "stimulated."
To place the child at the core of education is awesome, just as placing
the individual at the core of society was awesome when Jefferson wrote
it. It is also awful when it makes it commonsensical to make the child
in school, or the individual in society, the carrier of his own position
within the society.
At this point, I stop, because, after all, I am caught by the America
that has been constructed over the past centuries. Displacing the individual
from the institutional core is something that I cannot even propose: after
all, my critique is itself founded on the fear that America is dangerous
to individuals and thereby I have replaced the individual at the
core! It may be, optimistically, that the paradox I have been exploring
is not so much a contradiction as it is the very life force that keeps
America moving as its people explore new institutional ways to inscribe
individualism and community on the global landscape. In any event, America
is here to stay in all our futures, not only the future of my children
in the United States, but also the future of all around the globe, in
China, India, Africa. It will remain powerful as another way to being
human that will all human beings who learn about it, and will stand in
the way of even those who will continue searching for other ways. Of course,
I am not thinking here solely about economic, technological or military
power. I am thinking specifically about the ideological power that overwhelmed
earlier political ideologies in Europe and, later, arguably, in Russia
and perhaps even in China. Many, over the centuries, starting with the
French aristocrat de Tocqueville feared this power, or regretted what
it was sweeping away. Personally, I have not been sorry that I was placed
by the hazard of my personal history within the system, and indeed quite
close to its core. I have, obviously, been moving into the position of
the internal critic. But I take this position with all the respect due
to something much larger than myself that I continue to admire. I will
not dissociate myself from the goals of individual self-expression through
consensual communities and their schools. This experiment, America, has
not run its course.
|