The constitution of species is above all a means of grouping the facts so as to facilitate their interpretation, but social morphology is only one step towards the truly explanatory part of the science. What is the method appropriate for explanation? |
Most sociologists believe they have accounted for phenomena once they have demonstrated the
purpose they serve and the role they play. They reason as if phenomena existed solely for this role
and had no determining cause save a clear or vague sense of the services they are called upon to
render. This is why it is thought that all that is needful has been said to make them intelligible
when it has been established that these services are real and that the social need they satisfy has
been demonstrated. Thus Comte relates all the drive for progress of the human species to this
basic tendency, 'which directly impels man continually to improve his condition in all respects','
whereas Spencer relates it to the need for greater happiness. It is by virtue of this principle that
Spencer explains the formation of society as a function of the advantages which flow from
co-operation, the institution of government by the utility which springs from regulating military
co-operation, and the transformations which the family has undergone from the need for a more
perfect reconciliation of the interests of parents, children and society. |
1. Comte, Cours de philosophie positive, IV, p. 262. 2. Spencer, Principles of Sociology, vol. 11, part V, ch. II, p. 247. |
But this method confuses two very different questions. To demonstrate the utility of a fact does
not explain its origins, nor how it is what it is. The uses which it serves presume the specific
properties characteristic of it, but do not create it. Our need for things cannot cause them to be of
a particular nature; consequently, that need cannot produce them out of nothing, conferring in this
way existence upon them. They spring from causes of another kind. The feeling we have
regarding their utility can stimulate us to set these causes in motion and draw upon the effects
they bring in their train, but it cannot conjure up these results out of nothing. This proposition is
self-evident so long as only material or even psychological phenomena are being considered. It
would also not be disputed in sociology if the social facts, because of their total lack of material
substance, did not appear - wrongly, moreover bereft of intrinsic reality. Since we view them as
purely mental configurations, provided they are found to be useful, as soon as the idea of them
occurs to us they seem to be self-generating. But since each fact is a force which prevails over the
force of the individual and possesses its own nature, to bring a fact into existence it cannot suffice
to have merely the desire or the will to engender it. Prior forces must exist, capable of producing
this firmly established force, as well as natures capable of producing this special nature. Only
under these conditions can facts be created. To revive the family spirit where it has grown weak,
it is not enough for everybody to realise its advantages; we must set directly in operation those
causes which alone can engender it. To endow a government with the authority it requires, it is
not enough to feel the need for this. We must address ourselves to the sole sources from which all
authority is derived: the establishment o traditions, a common spirit, etc. For this we must retrace
our steps farther back along the chain of cause and effect until we find a point at which human
action can effectively intervene. |
|
What clearly demonstrates the duality of these two avenues of research is that a fact can exist
without serving any purpose, either because it has never been used to further any vital goal or
because, having once been of use, it has lost all utility but continues to exist merely through force
of custom. There are even more instances of such survivals in society than in the human organism.
There are even cases where a practice or a social institution changes its functions without for this
reason changing its nature. The rule of is pater est quem justae nuptiae declarant has remained
substantially the same in our legal code as it was in ancient Roman law. But while its purpose was
to safeguard the property rights of the father over children born of his legitimate wife, it is much
more the rights of the children that it protects today. The swearing of an oath began by being a
kind of judicial ordeal before it became simply a solemn and impressive form of attestation. The
religious dogmas of Christianity have not changed for centuries, but the role they play in our
modern societies is no longer the same as in the Middle Ages. Thus words serve to express new
ideas without their contexture changing. Moreover, it is a proposition true in sociology as in
biology, that the organ is independent of its function, i.e. while staying the same it can serve
different ends. Thus the causes which give rise to its existence are independent of the ends it
serves. |
|
Yet we do not mean that the tendencies, needs and desires of men never actively intervene in
social evolution. On the contrary, it is certain that, according to the way they make an impact
upon the conditions on which a fact depends, they can hasten or retard development. Yet, apart
from the fact that they can never create something out of nothing, their intervention itself,
regardless of its effects, can only occur by virtue of efficient causes. Indeed, a tendency cannot,
even to this limited extent, contribute to the production of a new phenomenon unless it is itself
new, whether constituted absolutely or arising from some transformation of a previous tendency.
For unless we postulate a truly providential harmony established beforehand, we could not admit
that from his origins man carried within him in potential all the tendencies whose opportuneness
would be felt as evolution progressed, each one ready to be awakened when the circumstances
called for it. Furthermore, a tendency is also a thing; thus it cannot arise or be modified for the
sole reason that we deem it useful. It is a force possessing its own nature. For that nature to come
into existence or be changed, it is not enough for us to find advantage in this occurring. To effect
such changes causes must come into play which require them physically. |
|
For example, we have explained the constant development of the social division of labour by
showing that it is necessary in order for man to sustain himself in the new conditions of existence
in which he is placed as he advances in history. We have therefore attributed to the tendency
which is somewhat improperly termed the instinct of self-preservation an important role in our
explanation. But in the first place the tendency alone could not account for even the most
rudimentary form of specialisation. it can accomplish nothing if the conditions on which this
phenomenon depends are not already realised, that is, if individual differences have not sufficiently
increased through the progressive state of indetermination of the common consciousness and
hereditary influences. 3 The division of labour must even have begun already to occur for its
utility to be perceived and its need to be felt. The mere development of individual differences,
implying a greater diversity of tastes and abilities, had necessarily to bring about this first
consequence. Moreover, the instinct of self-preservation did not come by itself and without cause
to fertilise this first germ of specialisation. If it directed first itself and then us into this new path, it
is because the course it followed and caused us to follow beforehand was as if blocked. This was
because the greater intensity of the struggle for existence brought about by the greater
concentration of societies rendered increasingly difficult the survival of those individuals who
continued to devote themselves to more unspecialised tasks . Thus a change of direction was
neces sary. On the other hand if it turned itself, and for preference turned our activity, towards an
ever increasing division of tabour, it was also because it was the path of least resistance. The
other possible solutions were emigration, suicide or crime. Now, on average, the ties that bind us
to our country, to life and to feeling for our fellows are stronger and more resistant sentiments
than the habits which can deter us from narrower specialisation. Thus these habits had inevitably
to give ground as every advance occurred. Thus, since we are ready to allow for human needs in
sociological explanations, we need not revert, even partially, to teleology. For these needs can
have no influence over social evolution unless they themselves evolve, and the changes through
which they pass can only be explained by causes which are in no way final. |
3. Division du travail social, 11, chs 3 and 4.
|
What is even more convincing that the foregoing argument is the study of how social facts work
out in practice. Where teleology rules, there rules also a fair margin of contingency, for there are
no ends - and even fewer means - which necessarily influence all men, even supposing they are
placed in the same circumstances. Given the same environment, each individual, according to his
temperament, adapts himself to it in the way he pleases and which he prefers to all others. The
one will seek to change it so that it better suits his needs; the other will prefer to change himself
and to moderate his desires. Thus to arrive at the same goal, many different routes can be, and in
reality are, followed. If then it were true that historical development occurred because of ends felt
either clearly or obscurely, social facts would have to present an infinite diversity and all
comparison would almost be impossible. But the opposite is true. Undoubtedly external events,
the links between which constitute the superficial part of social life, vary from one people to
another. Yet in this way each individual has his own history, although the bases of physical and
social organisation remain the same for all. If, in fact, one comes even a little into contact with
social phenomena, one is on the contrary surprised at the outstanding regularity with which they
recur in similar circumstances. Even the most trivial and apparently most puerile practices are
repeated with the most astonishing uniformity. A marriage ceremony, seemingly purely symbolic,
such as the abduction of the bride-to-be, is found to be identical everywhere that a certain type of
family exists, which itself is lined to a whole political organisation. The most bizarre customs,
such as the 'couvade', the levirate, exogamy, etc. are to be observed in the most diverse peoples
and are symptomatic of a certain social state. The right to make a will appears at a specific phase
of history and, according to the severity of the restrictions which limit it, we can tell at what stage
of social evolution we have arrived. It would be easy to multiply such examples. But the
widespread character of collective forms would be inexplicable if final causes held in sociology the
preponderance attributed to them. |
|
Therefore when one undertakes to explain a social phenomenon the efficient cause which
produces it and the function it fulfils must be investigated separately. We use the word 'function'
in preference to 'end' or 'goal' precisely because social phenomena generally do not exist for the
usefulness of the results they produce. We must determine whether there is a correspondence
between the fact being considered and the general needs of the social organism, and in what this
correspondence consists, without seeking to know whether it was intentional or not. All such
questions of intention are, moreover, too subjective to be dealt with scientifically. |
|
Not only must these two kinds of problems be dissociated from each other, but it is generally
appropriate to deal with the first kind before the second. This order of precedence corresponds
to that of the facts. It is natural to seek the cause of a phenomenon before attempting to determine
its effects. This method is all the more logical because the first question, once resolved, will often
help to answer the second. Indeed, the solid link which joins cause to effect is of a reciprocal
character which has not been sufficiently recognised. Undoubtedly the effect cannot exist without
its cause, but the latter, in turn, requires its effect. It is from the cause that the effect derives its
energy, but on occasion it also restores energy to the cause and consequently cannot disappear
without the cause 4 being affected. For example, the social reaction which constitutes punishment
is due to the intensity of the collective sentiments that crime offends. On the other hand it serves
the useful function of maintaining those sentiments at the same level of intensity, for they could
not fail to weaken if the offences committed against 5 them remained unpunished. Likewise, as
the social environment becomes more complex and unstable, traditions and accepted beliefs are
shaken and take on a more indeterminate and flexible character, whilst faculties of reflection
develop. These same faculties are indispensable for societies and individuals to adapt themselves
to a more mobile and complex environment.6 As men are obliged to work more intensively, the
products of their labour become more numerous and better in quality; but this increase in
abundance and quality of the products is necessary to compensate for the effort that this more
considerable labour entails .7 Thus, tar from the cause of social phenomena consisting of a mental
anticipation of the function they are called upon to fulfil, this function consists on the contrary, in
a number of cases at least, in maintaining the pre-existent cause from which the phenomena
derive. We will therefore discover more easily the function if the cause is already known. |
4. We would not wish to raise questions of general philosophy which would be inappropriate here. However, we note that, if more closely studied, this reciprocity of cause and effect could provide a means of reconciling scientific mechanism with the teleology implied by the existence and, above all, the persistence of life. 5. Division du travail social, 11, ch. 2, and especially pp.105ff. 6. Ibid., pp. 52-3. 7. Ibid., p. 301ff. |
If we must proceed only at a second stage to the determination of the function, it is none the less
necessary for the complete explanation of the phenomenon. Indeed, if the utility of a fact is not
what causes its existence, it must generally be useful to continue to survive. If it lacks utility, that
very reason suffices to make it harmful, since in that case it requires effort but brings in no return.
Thus if the general run of social phenomena had this parasitic character, the economy of the
organism would be in deficit, and social life would be impossible. Consequently to provide a
satisfactory explanation of social life we need to show how the phenomena which are its
substance come together to place society in harmony with itself and with the outside world.
Undoubtedly the present formula which defines life as a correspondence between the internal and
the external environments is only approximate. Yet in general it remains true; thus to explain a
fact which is vital, it is not enough to show the cause on which it depends. We must also - at least
in most cases - discover the part that it plays in the establishment of that general harmony. |
Having distinguished between these two questions, we must determine the method whereby they
must be resolved. | |
At the same time as being teleological, the method of explanation generally followed by
sociologists is essentially psychological. The two tendencies are closely linked. Indeed, if society
is only a system of means set up by men to achieve certain ends, these ends can only be individual,
for before society existed there could only exist individuals. It is therefore from the individual that
emanate the ideas and needs which have determined the formation of societies. If it is from him
that everything comes, it is necessarily through him that everything must be explained. Moreover,
in society there is nothing save individual consciousnesses, and it is consequently in these that is
to be found the source of all social evolution. Thus sociological laws can only be a corollary of
the more general laws of psychology. The ultimate explanation of collective life will consist in
demonstrating how it derives from human nature in general, either by direct deduction from it
without any preliminary observation, or by establishing links after having observed human nature. | |
These expressions are almost word for word those used by Auguste Comte to characterise his
method. 'Since the social phenomenon', he asserts, 'conceived of in its totality, is only basically a
simple development of humanity without any creation of faculties at all, as I have established
above, the whole framework of effects that sociological observation can successively uncover will
therefore necessarily be found, at least in embryo, in that primordial type which biology has
constructed beforehand for sociology'.8 This is because, in his view, the dominant fact of
social life is progress, and because progress furthermore depends on a factor exclusively psychical in
kind: the tendency that impels man to develop his nature more and more. Social facts may even
derive so immediately from human nature that, during the initial stages of history, they could be
directly deduced from it without having recourse to observation.9 It is true, as Comte concedes,
that it is impossible to apply this deductive method to the more advanced phases of evolution.
This impossibility is purely of a practical kind. It arises because the distance from the points of
departure and arrival becomes too considerable for the human mind, which, if it undertook to
traverse it without a guide, would run the risk of going astray. 10 But the relationship between
the basic laws of human nature and the ultimate results of progress is none the less capable of
analysis. The most complex forms of civilisation are only a developed kind of psychical life. Thus,
even if psychological theories cannot suffice as premises for sociological reasoning, they are the
touchstone which alone permits us to test the validity of propositions inductively established. 'No
law of social succession', declares Comte, 'which has been elaborated with all the authority
possible by means of the historical method, should be finally accepted before it has been rationally
linked, directly or indirectly, but always irrefutably, to the positivist theory of human nature.11
Psychology will therefore always have the last word. |
8. Comte, Cours de philosophie positive, IV, pp. 333-4. 9. Ibid., IV, p. 345. 10. Ibid., IV, p. 346. 11. Ibid., IV, p. 334. |
This is likewise the method followed by Spencer. In fact, according to him, the two primary
factors of social phenomena are the external environment and the physical and moral constitution
of the individual.[12] Now the first factor can only influence society through the second one, which
is thus the essential motivating power for social evolution. Society arises to allow the individual to
realise his own nature, and all the transformations through which it has passed have no other
purpose than to make this act of self-realisation easier and more complete. It is by virtue of this
principle that, before proceeding to any research into social Organisation, Spencer thought it
necessary to devote almost all the first volume of his Principles of Sociology to the study of
primitive man from the physical, emotional and intellectual viewpoint. 'The science of sociology',
he states, 'sets out with social units, conditioned as we have seen, constituted physically,
emotionally and intellectually and possessed of certain early acquired notions and correlative
feelings'.[13] And it is in two of these sentiments, fear of the living and fear of the dead, that he
finds the origin of political and religious government.[14] It is true that he admits that once it has
been constituted, society reacts upon individuals.[15] But it does not follow that society has the
power to engender directly the smallest social fact; from this viewpoint it has causal effectiveness
only through the mediation of the changes that it brings about in the individual. Thus it is always
from human nature, whether primitive or derived, that everything arises. Moreover, the influence
which the body social exerts upon its members can have nothing specific about it, since political
ends are nothing in themselves, but merely the summary expression of individual
ends.[16] Social influence can therefore only be a kind of consequent effect of private activity upon itself. Above
all, it is not possible to see of what it may consist in industrial societies whose purpose is precisely
to deliver the individual over to his natural impulses by ridding him of all social constraint. |
12. Spencer, Principles of Sociology,, vol. 1, part 1, ch. 2. 13. Ibid., vol. 1, part 1, ch. XXVII, p. 456. [Durkheim paraphrases. The exact quotation reads: 'Setting out with social units as thus conditioned physically, emotionally and intellectually, and as thus possessed of certain early-acquired ideas and correlative feelings, the science of sociology has to give an account of all the phenomena that result from their combined actions.] 14. Ibid., p. 456. 15. Ibid., p. 15. 16. 'Society exists for the benefit of its members; not its members for the benefit of society ... the claims of the body politic are nothing in themselves, and become something only in so far as they embody the claims of its component individuals' (vol.1, pt 11, ch. 11, pp. 479-80). |
This principle is not only at the basis of these great doctrines of general sociology, but also
inspires a very great number of particular theories. Thus domestic organisation is commonly
explained by the feelings that parents have for their children and vice versa; the institution of
marriage by the advantages that it offers husband and wife and their descendants; punishment by
the anger engendered in the individual through any serious encroachment upon his interests. The
whole of economic life, as conceived of and explained by economists, particularly those of the
orthodox school, hangs in the end upon a purely individual factor, the desire for wealth. If we
take morality, the basis of ethics is the duties of the individual towards himself. And in religion
one can see a product of the impressions that the great forces of nature or certain outstanding
personalities awaken in man, etc., etc. | |
But such a method is not applicable to sociological phenomena unless one distorts their nature.
For proof of this we need only refer to the definition we have given. Since their essential
characteristic is the power they possess to exert outside pressure on individual consciousnesses,
this shows that they do not derive from these consciousnesses and that consequently sociology is
not a corollary of psychology. This constraining power attests to the fact that they express a
nature different from our own, since they only penetrate into us by force or at the very least by
bearing down more or less heavily upon us. If social life were no more than an extension of the
individual, we would not see it return to its origin and invade the individual consciousness so
precipitately. The authority to which the individual bows when he acts, thinks or feels socially
dominates him to such a degree because it is a product of forces which transcend him and for
which he consequently cannot account. It is not from within himself that can come the external
pressure which he undergoes; it is therefore not what is happening within himself which can
explain it. It is true that we are not incapable of placing constraints upon ourselves; we can
restrain our tendencies, our habits, even our instincts, and halt their development by an act of
inhibition. But inhibitive movements must not be confused with those which make up social
constraint. The process of inhibitive movements is centrifugal; but the latter are centripetal. The
former are worked out in the individual consciousness and then tend to manifest themselves
externally; the latter are at first external to the individual, whom they tend afterwards to shape
from the outside in their own image. Inhibition is, if one likes, the means by which social
constraint produces its psychical effects, but is not itself that constraint. | |
Now, once the individual is ruled out, only society remains. It is therefore in the nature of society
itself that we must seek the explanation of social life. We can conceive that, since it transcends
infinitely the individual both in time and space, it is capable of imposing upon him the ways of
acting and thinking that it has consecrated by its authority. This pressure, which is the distinctive
sign of social facts, is that which all exert upon each individual ' | |
But it will be argued that since the sole elements of which society is composed are individuals, the
primary origin of sociological phenomena cannot be other than psychological. Reasoning in this
way, we can just as easily establish that biological phenomena are explained analytically by
inorganic phenomena. It is indeed certain that in the living cell there are only molecules of crude
matter. But they are in association, and it is this association which is the cause of the new
phenomena which characterise life, even the germ of which it is impossible to find in a single one
of these associated elements. This is because the whole does not equal the sum of its parts; it is
something different, whose properties differ from those displayed by the parts from which it is
formed. Association is not, as has sometimes been believed, a phenomenon infertile in itself, which
consists merely in juxtaposing externally facts already given and properties already constituted.
On the contrary, is it not the source of all the successive innovations that have occurred in the
course of the general evolution of things? What differences exist between the lower organisms
and others, between the organised living creature and the mere protoplasm, between the latter and
the inorganic molecules of which it is composed, if it is not differences in association? All these
beings, in the last analysis, split up into elements of the same nature; but these elements are in one
place juxtaposed, in another associated. Here they are associated in one way, there in another. We
are even justified in wondering whether this law does not even extend to the mineral world, and
whether the differences which separate inorganic bodies do not have the same origin. | |
By virtue of this principle, society is not the mere sum of individuals, but the system formed by
their association represents a specific reality which has its own characteristics. Undoubtedly no
collective entity can be produced if there are no individual consciousnesses: this is a necessary but
not a sufficient condition. In addition, these consciousnesses must be associated and combined,
but combined in a certain way. It is from this combination that social life arises and consequently
it is this combination which explains it. By aggregating together, by interpenetrating, by fusing
together, individuals give birth to a being, psychical if you will, but one which constitutes a
psychical individuality of a new kind. 17 Thus it is in the nature of that individuality and not in
that of its component elements that we must search for the proximate and determining causes of
the facts produced in it. The group thinks, feels and acts entirely differently from the way its
members would if they were isolated. If therefore we begin by studying these members separately,
we will understand nothing about what is taking place in the group. In a word, there is between
psychology and sociology the same break in continuity as there is between biology and the
physical and chemical sciences. Consequently every time a social phenomenon is directly
explained by a psychological phenomenon, we may rest assured that the explanation is false. |
17. In this sense and for these reasons we can and must speak of a collective consciousness distinct from individual consciousnesses. To justify this distinction there is no need to hypostatise the collective consciousness; it is something special and must be designated by a special term, simply because the states which constitute it differ specifically from those which make up individual consciousnesses. This specificity arises because they are not formed from the same elements. Individual consciousnesses result from the nature of the organic and psychical being taken in isolation, collective consciousnesses from a plurality of beings of this kind. The results cannot therefore fail to be different, since the component parts differ to this extent. Our definition of the social fact, moreover, did no more than highlight, in a different way, this demarcation line. |
Some will perhaps argue that, although society, once formed, is the proximate cause of social
phenomena, the causes which have determined its formation are of a psychological nature. They
may concede that, when individuals are associated together, their association may give rise to a
new life, but claim that this can only take place for individual reasons. But in reality, as far as one
can go back in history, the fact of association is the most obligatory of all, because it is the origin
of all other obligations. By reason of my birth, I am obligatorily attached to a given people. It may
be said that later, once I am an adult, I acquiesce in this obligation by the mere fact that I continue
to live in my own country. But what does that matter? Such acquiescence does not remove its
imperative character. Pressure accepted and undergone with good grace does not cease to be
pressure. Moreover, how far does such acceptance go? Firstly, it is forced, for in the immense
majority of cases it is materially and morally impossible for us to shed our nationality; such a
rejection is even generally declared to be apostasy. Next, the acceptance cannot relate to the past,
when I was in no position to accept, but which nevertheless determines the present. I did not seek
the education I received; yet this above all else roots me to my native soil. Lastly, the acceptance
can have no moral value for the future, in so far as this is unknown. I do not even know all the
duties which one day may be incumbent upon me in my capacity as a citizen. How then could I
acquiesce in them in advance? Now, as we have shown, all that is obligatory has its origins
outside the individual. Thus, provided one does not place oneself outside history, the fact of
association is of the same character as the others and is consequently explicable in the same way.
Furthermore, as all societies are born of other societies, with no break in continuity, we may be
assured that in the whole course of social evolution there has not been a single time when
individuals have really had to consult together to decide whether they would enter into collective
life together, and into one sort of collective life rather than another. Such a question is only
possible when we go back to the first origins of any society. But the solutions, always dubious,
which can be brought to such problems could not in any case affect the method whereby the facts
given in history must be treated. We have therefore no need to discuss them. | |
Yet our thought would be singularly misinterpreted if the conclusion was drawn from the previous
remarks that sociology, in our view, should not even take into account man and his faculties. On
the contrary, it is clear that the general characteristics of human nature play their part in the work
of elaboration from which social life results. But it is not these which produce it or give it its
special form: they only make it possible. Collective representations, emotions and tendencies have
not as their causes certain states of consciousness in individuals, but the conditions under which
the body social as a whole exists. Doubtless these can be realised only if individual natures are not
opposed to them. But these are simply the indeterminate matter which the social factor fashions
and transforms. Their contribution is made up exclusively of very general states, vague and thus
malleable predispositions which of themselves could not assume the definite and complex forms
which characterise social phenomena, if other agents did not intervene. | |
What a gulf, for example, between the feelings that man experiences when confronted with forces
superior to his own and the institution of religion with its beliefs and practices, so multifarious and
complicated, and its material and moral organisation! What an abyss between the psychical
conditions of sympathy which two people of the same blood feel for each other, 18 and that
hotchpotch of legal and moral rules which determine the structure of the family, personal
relationships, and the relationship of things to persons, etc.! We have seen that even when society
is reduced to an unorganised crowd, the collective sentiments which arise within it can not only be
totally unlike, but even opposed to, the average sentiments of the individuals in it. How much
greater still must be the gap when the pressure exerted upon the individual comes from a normal
society, where, to the influence exerted by his contemporaries, is added that of previous
generations and of tradition! A purely psychological explanation of social facts cannot therefore
fail to miss completely all that is specific, i.e. social, about them. |
18. Inasmuch as it may exist before all animal life. Cf. on this point, A. Espinas, Des societes animales, (Paris, 1877) p. 474. |
What has blinkered the vision of many sociologists to the insufficiency of this method is the fact
that, taking the effect for the cause, they have very often highlighted as causal conditions for
social phenomena certain psychical states, relatively well defined and specific, but which in reality
are the consequence of the phenomena. Thus it has been held that a certain religiosity is innate in
man, as is a certain minimum of sexual jealousy, filial piety or fatherly affection, etc., and it is in
these that explanations have been sought for religion, marriage and the family. But history shows
that these inclinations, far from being inherent in human nature, are either completely absent under
certain social conditions or vary so much from one society to another that the residue left after
eliminating all these differences, and which alone can be considered of psychological origin, is
reduced to something vague and schematic, infinitely removed from the facts which have to be
explained. Thus these sentiments result from the collective organisation and are far from being at
the basis of it. It has not even been proved at all that the tendency to sociability was originally a
congenital instinct of the human race. It is much more natural to see in it a product of social life
which has slowly become organised in us, because it is an observable fact that animals are sociable
or otherwise, depending on whether their environmental conditions force them to live in common
or cause them to shun such a life. And even then we must add that a considerable gap remains
between these well determined tendencies and social reality. | |
Furthermore, there is a means of isolating almost entirely the psychological factor, so as to be able
to measure precisely the scope of its influence: this is by seeking to determine how race affects
social evolution. Ethnic characteristics are of an organic and psychical order. Social life must
therefore vary as they vary, if psychological phenomena have on society the causal effectiveness
attributed to them. Now we know of no social phenomenon which is unquestionably dependent
on race, although we certainly cannot ascribe to this proposition the value of a law. But we can at
least assert that it is a constant fact in our practical experience. Yet the most diverse forms of
organisation are to be found in societies of the same race, while striking similarities are to be
observed among societies of different races. The city state existed among the Phoenicians, as it
did among the Romans and the Greeks; we also find it emerging among the Kabyles. The
patriarchal family was almost as strongly developed among the Jews as among the Hindus, but it
is not to be found among the Slavs, who are nevertheless of Aryan race. By contrast, the family
type to be found among the Slavs exists also among the Arabs. The maternal family and the clan
are observed everywhere. The precise nature of judicial proofs and nuptial ceremonies is no
different among peoples most unlike from the ethnic viewpoint. If this is so, it is because the
psychical element is too general to predetermine the course of social phenomena. Since it does not
imply one social form rather than another, it cannot explain any such forms. It is true that there
are a certain number of facts which it is customary to ascribe to the influence of race. Thus this, in
particular, is how we explain why the development of literature and the arts was so rapid and
intense in Athens, so slow and mediocre in Rome. But this interpretation of the facts, despite
being the classic one, has never been systematically demonstrated. It seems to draw almost all its
authority from tradition alone. We have not even reflected upon whether a sociological
explanation of the same phenomena was not possible, yet we are convinced that this might be
successfully attempted. In short, when we hastily attribute to aesthetic and inherited faculties the
artistic nature of Athenian civilisation, we are almost proceeding as did men in the Middle Ages,
when fire was explained by phlogiston and the effects of opium by its soporific powers. | |
Finally, if social evolution really had its origin in the psychological makeup of man, one fails to see
how this could have come about. For then we would have to admit that its driving force is some
internal motivation within human nature. But what might such a motivation be? Would it be that
kind of instinct of which Comte speaks, which impels man to realise increasingly his own nature?
But this is to reply to one question by another, explaining progress by an innate tendency to
progress, a truly metaphysical entity whose existence, moreover, has in no way been
demonstrated. For the animal species, even those of the highest order, are not moved in any way
by a need to progress, and even among human societies there are many which are content to
remain stationary indefinitely. Might it be, as Spencer seems to believe, that there is a need for
greater happiness, which forms of civilisation of every increasing complexity might be destined to
realise more and more completely? It would then be necessary to establish that happiness grows
with civilisation, and we have explained elsewhere all the difficulties to which such a hypothesis
gives rise. 19 Moreover, there is something else: even if one or other of these postulates were
conceded, historical development would not thereby become more intelligible; for the explanation
which might emerge from it would be purely teleological. We have shown earlier that social facts,
like all natural phenomena, are not explained when we have demonstrated that they serve a
purpose. After proving conclusively that a succession of social organisations in history which have
become increasingly more knowledgeable have resulted in the greater satisfaction of one or other
of our fundamental desires, we would not thereby have made the source of these organisations
more comprehensible. The fact that they were useful does not reveal to us what brought them into
existence. We might even explain how we came to conceive them, by drawing up a blueprint of
them beforehand, so as to envisage the services we might expect them to render - and this is
already a difficult problem. But our aspirations, which would thereby become the purpose of such
organisations, would have no power to conjure them up out of nothing. In short, if we admit that
they are the necessary means to attain the object we have in mind, the question remains in its
entirety: How, that is to say, from what, and in what manner, have these means been constituted? Hence we arrive at the following rule: The determining cause of a social fact must be sought
among antecedent social facts and not among the states of the individual consciousness.
Moreover, we can easily conceive that all that has been stated above applies to the determination
of the function as well as the cause of a social fact. Its function can only be social, which means
that it consists in the production of socially useful effects. Undoubtedly it can and indeed does
happen that it has repercussions which also serve the individual. But this happy result is not the
immediate rationale for its existence. Thus we can complement the preceding proposition by
stating: The function of a social fact must always be sought in the relationship that it bears to
some social end. It is because sociologists have often failed to acknowledge this rule and have considered
sociological phenomena from too psychological a viewpoint that their theories appear to many
minds too vague, too ethereal and too remote from the distinctive nature of the things which
sociologists believe they are explaining. The historian, in particular, who has a close contact with
social reality cannot fail to feet strongly how these too general interpretations are incapable of
being linked to the facts. In part, this has undoubtedly produced the mistrust that history has often
manifested towards sociology. Assuredly this does not mean that the study of psychological facts
is not indispensable to the sociologist. If collective life does not derive from individual life, the
two are none the less closely related. If the latter cannot explain the former, it can at least render
its explanation easier. Firstly, as we have shown, it is undeniably true that social facts are
produced by an elaboration sui generis of psychological facts. But in addition this action is itself not dissimilar to that which occurs in each individual consciousness and which
progressively transforms the primary elements (sensations, reflexes, instincts) of which the
consciousness was originally made up. Not unreasonably has the claim been made that the ego is
itself a society, just as is the organism, although in a different way. For a long time psychologists
have demonstrated the absolute importance of the factor of association in the explanation of
mental activity. Thus a psychological education, even more than a biological one, constitutes a
necessary preparation for the sociologist. But it can only be of service to him if, once he has
acquired it, he frees himself from it, going beyond it by adding a specifically sociological
education. He must give up making psychology in some way the focal point of his operations, the
point of departure to which he must always return after his adventurous incursions into the social
world. He must establish himself at the very heart of social facts in order to observe and confront
them totally, without any mediating factor, while calling upon the science of the individual only
for a general preparation and, if needs be, for useful suggestions. [20] |
19. Division du travail social, 11, ch. 1. 20. Psychical phenomena can only have social consequences when they are so closely linked to social phenomena that the actions of both are necessarily intermingled. This is the case for certain socio-psychical phenomena. Thus a public official is a social force, but at the same time he is an individual. The result is that he can employ the social force he commands in a way determined by his individual nature and thereby exert an influence on the constitution of society. This is what occurs with statesmen and, more generally, with men of genius. The latter, although they do not fulfil a social role, draw from the collective sentiments of which they are the object an authority which is itself a social force, one which they can to a certain extent place at the service of their personal ideas. But it can be seen that such cases are due to individual chance and consequently cannot affect the characteristics which constitute the social species, which alone is the object of science. The limitation on the principle enunciated above is therefore not of great importance to the sociologist. |
Since the facts of social morphology are of the same nature as physiological phenomena, they
must be explained according to the rule we have just enunciated. However, the whole of the
preceding discussion shows that in collective life and, consequently, in sociological explanations,
they play a preponderant role. | |
If the determining condition for social phenomena consists, as we have demonstrated, in the very fact of association, the phenomena must vary with the forms of that association, i.e. according to how the constituent elements in a society are grouped. Furthermore, since the distinct entity formed by the union of elements of all kinds which enter into the composition of a society constitutes its inner environment, in the same way as the totality of anatomical elements, together with the manner in which they are arranged in space, constitutes the inner environment of organisms, we may state: The primary origin of social processes of any importance must be sought in the constitution of the inner social environment. | |
We may be even more precise. In fact, the elements which make up this environment are of two
kinds: things and persons. Apart from the material objects incorporated in the society, among
things must be included the products of previous social activity the law and the customs that have
been established, and literary and artistic monuments, etc. But it is plain that neither material nor
non-material objects produce the impulsion that determines social transformations, because they
both lack motivating power. Undoubtedly there is need to take them into account in the
explanations which we attempt. To some extent they exert an influence upon social evolution
whose rapidity and direction vary according to their nature. But they possess no elements
essential to set that evolution in motion. They are the matter to which the vital forces of society
are applied, but they do not themselves release any vital forces. Thus the specifically human
environment remains as the active factor. | |
The principal effort of the sociologist must therefore be directed towards discovering the different
properties of that environment capable of exerting some influence upon the course of social
phenomena. Up to now we have found two sets of characteristics which satisfy that condition
admirably. These are: firstly, the number of social units or, as we have also termed it, the 'volume'
of the society; and secondly, the degree of concentration of the mass of people, or what we have
called the 'dynamic density'. The latter must be understood not only as the purely physical
concentration of the aggregate population, which can have no effect if individuals - or rather
groups of individuals - remain isolated by moral gaps, but the moral concentration of which
physical concentration is only the auxiliary element, and almost invariably the consequence.
Dynamic density can be defined, if the volume remains constant, as a function of the number of
individuals who are effectively engaged not only in commercial but also moral relationships with
each other, i.e. who not only exchange services or compete with one another, but live their life
together in common. For, since purely economic relationships leave men separated from each
other, these relationships can be very active without people necessarily participating in the same
collective existence. Business ties which span the boundaries which separate peoples do not make
those boundaries non-existent. The common life can be affected only by the number of people
who effectively co-operate in it. This is why what best expresses the dynamic density of a people
is the degree to which the social segments coalesce. For if each partial aggregate forms an entity,
a distinct individuality separated from the others by a barrier, it is because in general the activity
of its members remains localised within it. If, on the other hand, these 'partial entities are entirely
fused together, or tend to do so, within the total society, it is because the ambit of social life to
this extent has been enlarged. | |
As for the physical density - if this is understood as not only the number of inhabitants per unit of area, but also the development of the
means of communication and transmission - this is normally in proportion to
the dynamic density and, in general, can serve to measure it. For if the
different elements in the population tend to draw more closely together, it is inevitable that they will establish channels to allow this to occur.
Furthermore, relationships can be set up between remote points of the social mass only if distance does not represent an obstacle, which means, in fact,
that it must be eliminated. However, there are exceptions [21] and one would
expose oneself to serious error if the moral concentration of a community were always judged according to the degree of physical
concentration that it represented. Road, railways, etc. can serve commercial
exchanges better than they can serve the fusion of populations, of which
they can give only a very imperfect indication. This is the case in England,
where the physical density is greater than in France but where the coalescence of social segments is much less advanced, as is shown by the
persistence of parochialism and regional life. |
21. In our book, La Division du travail social, we were wrong to emphasise unduly physical density as being the exact expression of dynamic density. However, the substitution of the former for the latter is absolutely justified for everything relating to the economic effects of dynamic density, for instance the division of labour as a purely economic fact. |
We have shown elsewhere how every increase in the volume and dynamic density of societies, by
making social life more intense and widening the horizons of thought and action of each
individual, profoundly modifies the basic conditions of collective life. Thus we need not refer
again to the application we have already made of this principle. It suffices to add that the principle
was useful to us in dealing not only with the still very general question which was the object of
that study, but many other more specialised problems, and that we have therefore been able to
verify its accuracy already by a fair number of experiments. However, we are far from
believing that we have uncovered all the special features of the social environment which can play some part in the explanation of social facts. All
we can say is that these are the sole features we have identified and that we have not been led to
seek out others. | |
But the kind of preponderance we ascribe to the social environment, and more especially to the
human environment, does not imply that this should be seen as a kind of ultimate, absolute fact
beyond which there is no need to explore further. On the contrary, it is plain that its state at any
moment in history itself depends on social causes, some of which are inherent in society itself,
while others depend on the interaction occurring between that society and its neighbours.
Moreover, science knows no first causes, in the absolute sense of the term. For science a fact is
primary simply when it is general enough to explain a great number of other facts. Now the social
environment is certainly a factor of this kind, for the changes which arise within it, whatever the
causes, have repercussions on every part of the social organism and cannot fail to affect all its
functions to some degree. | |
What has just been said about the general social environment can be repeated for the particular
environments of the special groups which society includes. For example, depending on whether
the family is large or small, or more or less turned in upon itself, domestic life will differ
considerably. Likewise, if professional corporations reconstitute themselves so as to spread over a
whole area, instead of remaining enclosed within the confines of a city, as they formerly were,
their effect will be very different from what it was previously. More generally, professional life
will differ widely according to whether the environment peculiar to each occupation is strongly
developed or whether its bonds are loose, as is the case today. However, the effect of these
special environments cannot have the same importance as the general environment, for they are
subject to the latter's influence. Thus we must always return to the general environment. It is the
pressure that it exerts upon these partial groups which causes their constitution to vary. | |
This conception of the social environment as the determining factor in collective evolution is of
the greatest importance. For if it is discarded, sociology is powerless to establish any causal
relationship. | |
Indeed, if this order of causes is set aside, there are no concomitant conditions on which social
phenomena can depend. For if the external social environment - that which is formed by
neighbouring societies - is capable of exercising some influence, it is only upon the functions of
attack and defence; moreover, it can only make its influence felt through the mediation of the
internal social environment. The principal causes of historical development would not therefore be
found among the circumfusa (external influences). They would all be found in the past. They
would themselves form part of that development, constituting simply more remote phases of it.
The contemporary events of social life would not derive from the present state of society, but
from prior events and historical precedents, and sociological explanations would consist
exclusively in linking the present to the past. | |
It is true that this may seem sufficient. Is it not commonly said that the purpose of history is
precisely to link up events in their sequence? But it is impossible to conceive how the state which
civilisation has attained at any given time could be the determining cause of the state which
follows. The stages through which humanity successively passes do not engender each other. We
can well understand how the progress realised in a given era in the fields of law, economics and
politics, etc., makes fresh progress possible, but how does the one predetermine the other? The
progress realised is a point of departure which allows us to proceed further, but what stimulates
us to further progress? We would have to concede that there was a certain inner tendency which
impels humanity constantly to go beyond the results already achieved, either to realise itself more
fully or to increase its happiness, and the purpose of sociology would be to rediscover the order in
which this tendency has developed. But without alluding afresh to the difficulties which such a
hypothesis implies, in any case a law to express this development could not be in any sense causal.
A relationship of causality can in fact only be established between two given facts. But this
tendency, presumed to be the cause of development, is not something that is given. It is only
postulated as a mental construct according to the effects attributed to it. It is a kind of motivating
faculty which we imagine as underlying the movement which occurs, in order to account for it.
But the efficient cause of a movement can only be another movement, not a potentiality of this
kind. Thus all that we can arrive at experimentally is in point of fact a series of changes between
which there exists no causal link. The antecedent state does not produce the subsequent one, but
the relationship between them is exclusively chronological. In these conditions any scientific
prediction is thus impossible. We can certainly say how things have succeeded each other up the
present, but not in what order they will follow subsequently, because the cause on which they
supposedly depend is not scientifically determined, nor can it be so determined. It is true that
normally it is accepted that evolution will proceed in the same direction as in the past, but this is a
mere supposition. We have no assurance that the facts as they have hitherto manifested
themselves are a sufficiently complete expression of this tendency. Thus we are unable to forecast
the goal towards which they are moving in the light, of the stages through which they have
already successively passed. There is no reason to suppose that the direction this tendency follows
even traces out a straight line. | |
This is why the number of causal relationships established by sociologists is so limited. Apart from
a few exceptions, among whom Montesquieu is the most illustrious example, the former
philosophy of history concentrated solely on discovering the general direction in which humanity
was proceeding, without seeking to link the phases of that evolution to any concomitant
condition. Despite the great services Comte has rendered to social philosophy, the terms in which
he poses the sociological problem do not differ from those of his predecessors. Thus his
celebrated law of the three stages has not the slightest causal relationship about it. Even if it were
true, it is, and can only be, empirical. It is a summary review of the past history of the human race.
It is purely arbitrary for Comte to consider the third stage to be the definitive stage of humanity.
Who can say whether another will not arise in the future.? Similarly, the law which dominates the
sociology of Spencer appears to be no different in nature. Even if it were true that we at present
seek our happiness in an industrial civilisation, there is no assurance that, at a later era, we shall
not seek it elsewhere. The generality and persistence of this method is due to the fact that very
often the social environment has been perceived as a means whereby progress has been realised,
and not the cause which determines it. | |
Furthermore, it is also in relationship to this same environment that must be measured the
utilitarian value, or as we have stated it, the function of social phenomena. Among the changes
caused by the environment, those are useful which are in harmony with the existing state of
society, since the environment is the essential condition for collective existence. Again, from this
viewpoint the conception we have just expounded is, we believe, fundamental, for it alone allows
an explanation of how the useful character of social phenomena can vary without depending on
arbitrary factors. If historical evolution is envisaged as being moved by a kind of vis a tergo (vital
urge) which impels men forward, since a dynamic tendency can have only a single goal, there can
exist only one reference point from which to calculate the utility or harmfulness of social
phenomena. It follows that there exists, and can only exist, a single type of social organisation
which fits humanity perfectly, and the different societies of history are only successive
approximations to that single model. It is unnecessary to show how such a simplistic view is today
irreconcilable with the acknowledged variety and complexity of social forms. If on the other hand
the suitability or unsuitability of institutions can only be established in relation to a given
environment, since these environments are diverse, a diversity of reference points thus exists, and
consequently a diversity of types which, whilst each being qualitatively distinct, are all equally
grounded in the nature of the social environment. | |
The question just dealt with is therefore closely connected to the constitution of social types. If
there are social species, it is because collective life depends above all on concomitant conditions
which present a certain diversity. If, on the contrary, the main causes of social events were all in
the past, every people would be no more than the extension of the one preceding it, and different
societies would lose their individuality, becoming no more than various moments in time of one
and the same development. On the other hand, since the constitution of the social environment
results from the mode in which the social aggregates come together - and the two phrases are in
the end synonymous - we have now the proof that there are no characteristics more essential than
those we have assigned as the basis for sociological classification. | |
Finally, we should now realise better than before how unjust it would be to rely on the terms 'external conditions' and 'environment' to serve as an indictment of our method, and seek the sources of life outside what is already alive. On the contrary, the considerations just mentioned lead us back to the idea that the causes of social phenomena are internal to the society. It is much rather the theory which seeks to derive society from the individual that could be justly reproached with seeking to deduce the internal from the external (since it explains the social being by something other than itself) and the greater from the lesser (since it undertakes to deduce the whole from the part). Our own preceding principles in no way fail to acknowledge the spontaneous character of every living creature: thus, if they are applied to biology and psychology, it will have to be admitted that individual life as well develops wholly within the individual. |
From the set of rules which has just been established, there arises a certain conception of society
and collective life. | |
Two opposing theories divide men on this question. | |
For some, such as Hobbes and Rousseau, there is a break in continuity between the individual and
society. Man is therefore obdurate to the common life and can only resign himself to it if forced to
do so. Social ends are not simply the meeting point for individual ends; they are more likely to run
counter to then. Thus, to induce the individual to pursue social ends, constraint must be exercised
upon him, and it in the institution and organisation of this constraint that lies the supreme task of
society. Yet because the individual is regarded as the sole and unique reality of the human
kingdom, this organisation, which is designed to constrain and contain him, can only be conceived
of as artificial. The organisation is not grounded in nature, since it is intended to inflict violence
upon him by preventing him from producing anti-social consequences. It is an artifact, a machine
wholly constructed by the hands of men and which, like all products of this kind, is only what it is
because men have willed it so; an act of volition created it, another one can transform it. Neither
Hobbes nor Rousseau appear to have noticed the complete contradiction that exists in admitting
that the individual is himself the creator of a machine whose essential role is to exercise
domination and constraint over him. Alternatively, it may have seemed to them that, in order to
get rid of this contradiction, it was sufficient to conceal it from the eyes of its victims by the skilful
device of the social contract. | |
It is from the opposing idea that the theoreticians of natural law and the economists, and more
recently Spencer,[22] have drawn their inspiration. For them social life is essentially spontaneous and
society is a natural thing. But, if they bestow this characteristic upon it, it is not because they
acknowledge it has any specific nature, but because they find a basis for it in the nature of the
individual. No more than the two thinkers already mentioned do they see in it a system of things
which exists in itself, by virtue of causes peculiar to itself. But while Hobbes and Rousseau only
conceived it as a conventional arrangement, with no link at all in reality, which, so to speak, is
suspended in air, they in turn state its foundations to be the fundamental instincts of the human
heart. Man is naturally inclined to political, domestic and religious life, and to commercial
exchanges, etc., and it is from these natural inclinations that social organisation is derived.
Consequently, wherever it is normal, there is no need to impose it by force. Whenever it resorts to
constraint it is because it is not what it ought to be, or because the circumstances are abnormal. In
principle, if individual forces are left to develop untrammelled they will organise themselves
socially. |
22. The position of Comte on this subject is one of a pretty ambiguous eclecticism. |
Neither of these doctrines is one we share. Doubtless we make constraint the characteristic trait of every social fact. Yet this constraint does not arise from some sort of artful machination destined to conceal from men the snares into which they have stumbled. It is simply due to the fact that the individual finds himself in the presence of a force which dominates him and to which he must bow. But this force is a natural one. It is not derived from some conventional arrangement which the human will has contrived, adding it on to what is real; it springs from the heart of reality itself; it is the necessary product of given causes. Thus to induce the individual to submit to it absolutely of his own free will, there is no need to resort to deception. It is sufficient to make him aware of his natural state of dependence and inferiority. Through religion he represents this state to himself by the senses or symbolically; through science he arrives at an adequate and precise notion of it. Because the superiority that society has over him is not merely physical, but intellectual and moral, it need fear no critical examination, provided this is fairly undertaken. Reflection which causes man to understand how much richer or more complex and permanent the social being is than the individual being, can only reveal to him reasons to make comprehensible the subordination which is required of him and for the feelings of attachment and respect which habit has implanted within him.[23] Thus only singularly superficial criticism could lay us open to the reproach that our conception of social constraint propagates anew the theories of Hobbes and Machiavelli. But if, contrary to these philosophers, we say that social life is natural, it is not because we find its origin in the nature of the individual; it is because it derives directly from the collective being which is, of itself, a nature sul . generis; it is because it arises from that special process of elaboration which individual consciousnesses undergo through their association with each other and whence evolves a new form of existence.[24] If therefore we recognise with some authorities that social life presents itself to the individual under the form of constraint, we admit with others that it is a spontaneous product of reality. What logically joins these two elements, in appearance contradictory, is that the reality from which social life emanates goes beyond the individual. Thus these words, 'constraint' and ,spontaneity', have not in our terminology the respective meanings that Hobbes gives to the former and Spencer to the second. To summarise: to most of the attempts that have been made to explain social facts rationally, the
possible objection was either that they did away with any idea of social discipline, or that they
only succeeded in maintaining it with the assistance of deceptive subterfuges. The rules we have
set out would, on the other hand, allow a sociology to be constructed which would see in the
spirit of discipline the essential condition for all common life, while at the same time founding it
on reason and truth. | 23. This is why all constraint is not normal. Only that constraint which corresponds to some social superiority, intellectual or moral, merits that designation. But that which one individual exercises over another because he is stronger or richer, above all if this wealth does not express his social worth, is abnormal and can only be maintained by violence. 24. Our theory is even more opposed to Hobbes than that of natural law. Indeed, for the supporters of this latter doctrine, collective life is only natural in so far as it can be deduced from the nature of the individual. Now only the most general forms of social organisation can at a pinch be derived from that origin. As for the details of social organisation, these are too far removed from the extreme generality of psychical properties to be capable of being linked to them. They therefore appear to the disciples of this school just as artificial as to their adversaries. For us, on the contrary, everything is natural, even the strangest arrangements, for everything is founded on the nature of society. |