Henry Giroux |
Ideology, culture and the process of schooling |
Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press. 1981. |
Though there exists no fully developed theory of hegemony,6z the starting
point for studying the concept has to begin with the work of Antonio Gramsci.63
Writing in the wake of economic upheavals, revolutionary struggles, and the
rise of fascism in the early decades of the twentieth century in Italy, Gramsci
attempted to redefine and redirect the central tenets of Marxist theory. Rejecting
the orthodox Marxist faith in objective economic forces and scientific laws,
Gramsci i turned his attention to the voluntarist side of Marxist theory.
He strongly argued that the domination of capital could not be explained by
simply pointing to the rule of force and coercion exercised by the capitalist
state. Similarly, he argued that revolutionary struggle could not be relegated
to a faith in the inevitable breakdown and self destruction of capitalism's
inner logic and laws. For Gramsci the historical materialism of orthodox Marxism
was blinded by its own wooden metaphors and paralyzed by its economistic straitjacket.
Neither political force nor the logic of capitalist development provided the
theoretical basis for fully understanding or changing the nature of capitalist
society. Gramsci believed that a more suitable approach would have been to
take the notion of consciousness more seriously. That is, the assumption that
human beings become political actors as they move through and create the 'terrain
on which men move, [and] acquire consciousness of their position, struggle'.64
It is this link between struggle, domination, and liberation, on the one side,
and Gramsci's view of the power of consciousness and ideology on the other,
that establishes the problematic for understanding his notion of hegemony.
Hegemony as it is used by Gramsci appears to have two meanings.65 First, it
refers to a process within civil society whereby a fundamental class exercises
control though its moral and intellectual leadership over allied classes.
In this perspective an alliance is formed among ruling groups as a result
of the power and 'ability of one class to articulate the interest of other
social groups to its own'.66 Gramsci appears very clear in pointing out that
the intellectual and moral leadership exercised by the dominant class does
not consist of the imposition of its own ideology upon allied groups. Instead,
it represents a pedagogic and politically transformative process whereby the
dominant class articulates a hegemonic principle that brings together common
elements drawn from the world views and interests of allied groups. The second
use of the term takes on a much more dynamic character. Hegemony, as it is
used in this case, points to the relationship between the dominant and dominated
classes. In this case, hegemony refers to the successful attempt of a dominant
class to utilize its control over the resources of state and civil society,
particularly through the use of the mass media and the educational system,61
to establish its view of the world as all inclusive and universal. Through
the dual use of force and consent, with consent prevailing, the dominant class
uses its political, moral, and intellectual leadership to shape and incorporate
the 'taken-for-granted' views, needs, and concerns of subordinate groups.
In doing so, the dominant class not only attempts to influence the interests
and needs of such groups, it also contains radical opportunities by placing
limits on oppositional discourse and practice. As Douglas Kellner observes,
'hegemonic ideologies attempt to define the limits of discourse, by setting
the political agenda, by defining the issues and terms of debate, and by excluding
oppositional ideas'. 6$
One important feature of hegemonic rule is that it refers to more than the
institutionalization and framing of specific modes of discourse; it also includes
the messages inscribed in material practices. Put another way, hegemony is
rooted in both the meanings and symbols that legitimate dominant interests
as well as in the practices that structure daily experience. That hegemony
functions, for example, through the significations embedded in school texts,
films, and 'official' teacher discourse is clear enough. What is less obvious
is that it also functions in those practical experiences that need no discourse,
the message of which lingers beneath a stuctured silence. Pierre Bourdieu
captures this issue with his comment:
. . . the most successful ideological effects are those which have no need
of words, and ask no more than complicitous silence. It follows . . . that
any analysis of ideologies, in the narrow sense of 'legitimating j
discourses', which fails to include an analysis of the corresponding in- ',
stitutional mechanisms is liable to be no more than a contribution to the
efficacy of those ideologies.69
And in another observation worth quoting at length:
The whole trick of pedagogic reason lies precisely in the way it extorts
the essential while seeming to demand the insignificant: in obtaining the
respect for form and forms of respect which constitute the most visible (and
at the same time best hidden because most 'natural') manifestation of submission
to the established order . . . that is, all the eccentricities and deviations
which are the small change of madness.1°
In schools, as in other institutions, the production of hegemonic ideologies
'hides' behind a number of legitimating forms. Some of the most obvious include:
(1) the claim by dominant classes that their interests represent the entire
interests of the community; (2) the claim that conflict only occurs outside
of the sphere of the political, i.e., economic conflict is viewed as non-political;
(3) the presentation of specific forms of consciousness, beliefs, attitudes,
values and practices as natural, universal, or even eternal.
To suggest that hegemony is entered into by both the dominated and the dominant
classes raises significant questions about the role that the dominated play
in contributing to their own oppression and about the nature of hegemony itself.
But in order to unravel such questions, the contradictory nature of ideological
hegemony must be laid bare. That is, it is important to demonstrate that hegemony
in any of its forms or processes does not represent a cohesive force. Instead,
it is riddled with contradictions and tensions that open up the possibility
for counter-hegemonic struggle as well as reinforce the distinction between
hegemony and ideology.
The very structure of the ruling class, for instance, makes it almost impossible
for a unified hegemonic ideology to prevail over a given society, particularly
in the advanced industrial countries of the West. Althusser's Ideological
State Apparatus is not dominated by simply one group, as previously mentioned,
it is ruled by an alliance of powerful groups who are constantly shifting
and changing the form and content of their legitimating interests as historical
circumstances change and new forms of resistance emerge." Moreover, as
Aronowitz points out, ruling classes do not produce and disseminate ideologies
directly; instead, they appropriate the services of intellectuals and other
cultural workers who have the creativity and skills to organize and run cultural
apparatuses such as schools and the organs of mass media.7z On the one hand,
this limits the control that the dominant classes have over such cultural
sectors. On the other hand, it also provides such institutions with the relative
autonomy that makes possible the gaps, tensions, and modes of resistance that
contain a critique of the hegemonic order.73 This position takes on added
meaning in Gouldner's comment:
It is precisely because the hegemonic elite is separated from the means of
culture, including the production of ideologies, that ideologies developed
in capitalist society may often be discomforting to the hegemonic elite, so
that they prefer other methods of dominance and integration more fully and
routinely accessible to them.74
Similarly, in addition to hegemony not being a cohesive force, it is a mode
of control that has to be fought for constantly in order to be maintained.
In other words, it is not something 'that simply consists of the projection
of the ideas of the dominant class into the heads of the subordinate classes'.7s
The terrain on which hegemony moves and functions has constantly to shift
ground in order to accommodate the changing nature of historical circumstances
and the demands and reflexive actions of human beings. This issue is highlighted
in Gramsci's notion of 'contradictory consciousness'. Gramsci meant by the
latter that human beings view the world from a perspective that contains both
hegemonic forms of thinking and modes of critical insight. In other words,
'contradictory consciousness' represented a form of common sense that was
rooted in folklore, but at the same time enriched 'with scientific ideas and
philosophical opinions which have entered ordinary life'.76 In Gramsci's view
the consciousness of ordinary people could not be equated with passivity and
one-dimensionality. Instead, it had to be seen as a complex combination of
thought and practice 'unable to break with the given world and transform it'.77
Far from being simply the reflex of defeat and passivity, such a consciousness
is fragmented and ambivalent. Or to put it another way:
. . . on an abstract level, the masses manifest a great deal of agreement
with the dominant ideology, but this consensus is superficial and coexists
with latent instincts of rebellion, which are often expressd in deviant behavior
and which compromises, in embryonic form, an alternative Weltanschauung. 78
This perception of hegemony redefines class rule, and also reveals a relationship
between ideology and power, which is viewed not simply as one of imposition
but, as Foucault points out, 'a network of relations, constantly in tension,
in activity, rather than a privilege one might possess . . . power is exercised
rather than possessed'.79 Power as used here is a form of production, which
rather than constrain the subject, becomes its constituting feature. Ideology
as an element of hegemony points then to one's limited perception of the world
and to social practices that mold and shape the structure of dispositions
and needs as well. Thus, power represents both a negative and positive moment.
As a negative moment, it strips ideology of its critical possibilities and
institutionalizes it as a form of hegemony. As a positive moment, it refers
to latent as well as manifest modes of critical discourse and practice which
constitute the core of ideology.
The duality of power and control represents a crucial concept for viewing
sites such as schools as instances of both hegemonic and counter- hegemonic
struggles. Gramsci's notion that hegemony represents a pedagogical relationship
through which the legitimacy of meaning and practice is struggled over makes
it imperative that a theory of radical pedagogy take as its central task an
analysis of how both hegemony functions in schools and how various forms of
resistance and opposition either challenge or help to sustain it.
Hegemony and ideology represent important concepts in educational theory
and practice because they expose the political nature of schooling and point
to possibilities for developing alternative modes of pedagogy. However, helpful
as these concepts are in the end, they are incomplete because they do not
provide the theoretical framework for developing a notion of totality that
reveals how a society reproduces and mediates the wide range of conflicting
social formations, ideologies, and structures that either give it a specific
historical location or expose its underlying determinations. For this we have
to turn to the concept of culture.